Keyboard Shortcuts?f

×
  • Next step
  • Previous step
  • Skip this slide
  • Previous slide
  • mShow slide thumbnails
  • nShow notes
  • hShow handout latex source
  • NShow talk notes latex source

Click here and press the right key for the next slide.

(This may not work on mobile or ipad. You can try using chrome or firefox, but even that may fail. Sorry.)

also ...

Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)

Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)

Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)

Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts

 

Dual Process Theory Opposes Decision Theory?

essay question

Which, if any, applications of decision theory are incompatible with the truth of Dickinson’s dual process theory of action?

habitual process

Action occurs in the presence of Stimulus.

Outcome follows action

Agent is thereby rewarded

Stimulus-Action Link is strengthened due to reward

Given Stimulus, will Action occur? It depends on the strength of the Stimulus-Action Link.

‘goal-directed’ process

Action leads to Outcome.
 

Belief in Action-Outcome link is strengthened.

Agent has a Desire for the Outcome
 

Will Action occur? It depends on the Belief in the Action-Outcome Link and Agent’s Desire.

What are these beliefs and desires? How exactly do they lead to actions? I suggested that we can appeal to decision theory for an answer to both questions.
I suggested that we take game theory as elucidating the goal-directed process.

This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’

(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)

key assumption:

Agents’ actions maximise their expected utilities.

This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’

(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)

key assumption:

Agents’ actions maximise their expected utilities.

If we understand this as instrumental action, we run into a problem ...

habitual process

Action occurs in the presence of Stimulus.

Outcome follows action

Agent is thereby rewarded

Stimulus-Action Link is strengthened due to reward

Given Stimulus, will Action occur? It depends on the strength of the Stimulus-Action Link.

‘goal-directed’ process

Action leads to Outcome.
 

Belief in Action-Outcome link is strengthened.

Agent has a Desire for the Outcome
 

Will Action occur? It depends on the Belief in the Action-Outcome Link and Agent’s Desire.

Not all of the processes which influence action are processes that maximise expected utilties.
After all, there are habitual processes.

This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’

(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)

key assumption:

Agents’ actions maximise their expected utilities.

objection:

The assumption is unjustified given the dual-process theory.

Note that formulating the objection properly is quite tricky.
One way to formulate it is to ask whether the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability are supposed to be those which feature in the goal-directed process.
If they are, then the existence of habitual processes entails that the assumption that agents’ actions maximise their expected utilities is false.
If they are not, then we currently lack a way to identify psychological counterparts of the decision-theoretic notions, and so to transition from a merely descriptive model to a theory capable of explaining why people act.
So this is the objection. Agents’ actions do not actually maximise their expected utilties.
Is it a good objection?
Not yet. But can you make a good objection here? (I will try myself in a moment.)
These claims cannot all be true (inconsistent set)

1. Decision theory provides an ‘elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’ (Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi).

2. These notions feature in the goal-directed process, which maximises expected utility.

3. Some instrumental actions are dominated by habitual processes.

4. Habitual and goal-directed processes can pull in opposing directions.

therefore:

5. Some actions do not maximise expected utility. [So (1) is false]

Key is that these claims undermine any basis for expecting the actual choices made to respect the axioms.
Which claim can we reject?
Explain significance of this claim: you can have things finely balanced so that, with no change in preferences, sometimes habitual dominate and sometimes goal-directed dominate, and yet the two lead to different actions. Since preferences are unchanged, there cannot be a change in expected utility; and yet there is a change in action.
Can reject this one.
The problem, though, is that this was the very thing we wanted to elucidate. So we would then face the problem that we do not know what the notions of belief and desire are as they feature in the goal-directed process.

response 1

‘the laws of decision theory (or any other theory of rationality) are not empirical generalisations about all agents. What they do is define what is meant ... by being rational’

(Davidson, 1987, p. 43)

but: elucidation was our goal

This is maybe fine if you want to use decision theory like that.
But we wanted to use it to elucidate states which play a role in a theory that offers a causal explanation of action.
So it’s important for us that the elucidation explains what it is for a particular individual to have a particular preference. (It’s maybe not impossible to do this by talking about ideally rational agents but that is another response (response 4 below about distinguishing computational from implementation levels).)
So this response really just concedes the objection.
[UPDATE: I’m a bit worried about this. Isn’t Davidson close to Jeffries. Doesn’t he somehow think that they are not empirical generalisations and also that they (or a theory based on them) characterise the notions of belief and desire? He seems to have it both ways by imposing a Principle of Rationality? So maybe the thought is that we can understand the psychological states by identifying the ideal to which they are supposed to match? In which case this is like the `compuatational description` response below. I think what I say here is fine though: simply switching from elucidation to defining what is meant my rational REALLY IS changing the subject. (I’m just not saying that this is what Davidson actually does.)]
[UPDATE 2: Actually I think Davidson never faced up to the problem and that the Principle of Charity and Rationality stuff was maybe not worked out in any detail given that there are *systematic* failures to conform to the axioms?]
But this is important because it shows that ...

We are not objecting to decision theory.

We are objecting to a particular application of it (as an elucidation).

application 1: decision theory provides ‘mathematically complete principles which define “rational behavior”’

application 2: decision theory provides an elucidation of belief and desire

NB: the claim is that decision theory provides an elucidation of belief and desire *as featured in goal-directed processes*. (So strictly speaking Jeffrey might have succeeded in elucidating the notions he was interested in.)
Interesting side question is whether the narrowly normative application can stand. After all, it seems to require that what subjects are optimising is utilities specified in ways that do not reflect the beliefs and desires that feature in the goal-directed process.
I am not going to consider that further but I do think there is an opportunity for some original research on the basis for a normative application of decision theory as defining rational behaviour.

essay question

Which, if any, applications of decision theory are incompatible with the truth of Dickinson’s dual process theory of action?

response 2

It’s an approximation; the details don’t matter.

This is tempting because habitual processes will tend, when things to well, to maximise expected utilities.
We might even see decision theory as characterising what the habitual processes are a shortcut to achieving.

but: prediction vs elucidation

This might be a fine response if we were using decision theory to predicting behaviour.
Sometimes you gain predictive power by abstracting from messy impelementation details.
And **seen from the outside**, agents will likely behave much as if they were maximising their expected utiltities.
But our aim was to elucidate the notions of belief and desire as they feature in an explanation of action. To do that, we have to identify them with the theoretical constructs of decision theory.
If agents’ actions do not conform to the axioms (transitivity of preferences etc), then they lack beliefs and desires. And so our theory fails to elucidate the things we wanted it to elucidate.
So this second response also really just conceeds the objection. It distracts us by pointing to other applications of decision theory. But we were not objecting that decision theory has no other applications. We were objecting to a specific application of it.

response 3

What maximises expected utility are not actions but goal-directed processes.

At one time this was the most interesting line of response I know. It offers a substantial change to the construal of decision theory but also attempts to avoid the objection.

This book has ‘a philosophical end: elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’

(Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi)

key assumption:

Agents’ actions goal-directed processes maximise their expected utilities.

habitual process

Action occurs in the presence of Stimulus.

Outcome follows action

Agent is thereby rewarded

Stimulus-Action Link is strengthened due to reward

Given Stimulus, will Action occur? It depends on the strength of the Stimulus-Action Link.

‘goal-directed’ process

Action leads to Outcome.
 

Belief in Action-Outcome link is strengthened.

Agent has a Desire for the Outcome
 

Will Action occur? It depends on the Belief in the Action-Outcome Link and Agent’s Desire.

problem now is that preferences feature twice in the scheme of things!
Is the preference that dictates the reward the same or different?

Concerning the habitual process, what makes outcomes rewarding?

possibility 1:

the very system of preference that is involved in the goal-directed process

possibility 2:

not the system of preference that is involved in the goal-directed process

Each has potential problems.
possibility 1: if this is right, decision theory did not provide a full elucidation of the notion of preference. So we have discovered something substantial: decision theory provides at most a partical elucidation. And it is unclear how to develop the elucidation further.
possibility 2: now it looks like the two processes might pull in different directions. What if anything ensures that they are not fighting against each other in the way that people with different preferences might? (My habitual processes love bananas and hate chocolate ...)
While this may seem really unlikely, we will actually see some support for possibility 2 later in course. One rule of thumb for philosophy: never rule something out on the basis that it seems implausible.

response 4

distinguish computational theory from implementation details

[This is currently what I take to be the most promising response.]
Both habitual and goal-directed processes are supposed to maximise expected utility.
Each does so only within limits and so involves risks of error.
But the limits are a matter of the implementation (speed--accuracy trade-offs). They are not part of the computational description.
If this is right, there is no need to suppose that agents’ actions actually conform to the axioms. Just that they are in some sense supposed to do so, that this is an aim of the various processes involved in action selection.
But there is a cost, of course: to characterise the notions we need not only the computational theory but also at least some idea of how the implementation details could go.
You could think of the characterisation of the habitual process as describing this.
But what is the corresponding characterisation of the goal-directed process? I guess we have in mind some kind of algorithm for computing expected utility? Which may itself involve short cuts?

How to implement a utility maximizing agent?

option 1: search through potential actions, imagine consequences, evaluate how good they’d be

option 2: estimate best action from past rewards

option 3: combine 1 and 2

Having two processes
allows you to make complementary
speed--accuracy trade-offs:
habitual processes are fast but limited, whereas goal-directed processes are more flexible but slower

Any broadly computational system will face ...

response 4

distinguish computational theory from implementation details

response 5

seek an alternative

‘Expected utility theory [...] has come under serious question [...]

There is now general agreement that the theory does not provide an adequate description of individual choice: a substantial body of evidence shows that decision makers systematically violate its basic tenets.

Many alternative models have been proposed’

(Tversky & Kahneman, 1992, p. 297)

But can the alternatives elucidate notions of belief and desire?

response 6

they do not exist

‘The problem with measuring risk preferences is not that measurement is difficult and inaccurate; it is that there are no risk preferences to measure—there is simply no answer to how, ‘deep down’, we wish to balance risk and reward.

And, while we’re at it, the same goes for the way people trade off present against future; how altruistic we are and to whom; how far we display prejudice on gender, race, and so on ...

there is no point wondering which way of asking the question [...] will tell us what people really want.

there can be no method...that can conceivably answer this question, not because our mental motives, desires and preferences are impenetrable, but because they don’t exist

(Chater, 2018, pp. 123--4)

1. Decision theory provides an ‘elucidation of the notions of subjective probability and subjective desirability or utility’ (Jeffrey, 1983, p. xi).

2. These notions feature in the goal-directed process, which maximises expected utility.

3. Some instrumental actions are dominated by habitual processes.

4. Habitual and goal-directed processes can pull in opposing directions.

therefore:

5. Some actions do not maximise expected utility.

This is a lecture with various elements that can be assembled into slightly different arguments.
This is not the order of the lecture but the biggest argument, which I will focus on.
characterising belief + desire is a problem decision theory offers a solution the dual-proces theory of instrumental action entails that the solution is wrong we cannot use decision theory to characterise belief and desire

conclusion

In conclusion, ...

What decision theory is

and how could provide us as researchers with a shared understanding of belief and desire.

Why we need an anchor for belief and desire,

and the difficulty of combining decision theory’s elucidation with the existence of both habitual and goal-directed processes.

you should now be able to answer this essay question

essay question

Which, if any, applications of decision theory are incompatible with the truth of Dickinson’s dual process theory of action?

next steps

challenge

Discover why people act,
individually and jointly.